There is in fact one prominent group of critics who agree completely that it is the realistic nature of simulations that make them problematic. A plethora of concerned citizens groups, soapbox psychologists and their legislative panderers routinely castigate electronic games for their putative ability to influence the behavior of gamers in negative ways. The power of these games, the argument goes, lies chiefly in their realistic nature, and the way in which their violent content doesnt simply model behavior for their clientele (in the way that movies do, according to the argument mounted in parallel by the same groups), but allows gamers to, in essence, practice the behavior by participating in the realistic environments in which it is employed. Now this argument is clearly rubbish, and Frasca himself has provided one of the wittiest denunciations of this proposition. He has argued that the amount of social harm that games may have perpetrated is as nothing when compared with the horrors unleashed on the world by people who have been inspired by books (Mein Kampf, Maos Little Red Book, the Bible, Pamela. . . ):
Moral crusaders allude to (without, usually, referencing) a supposed superfluity of research that provides damning evidence of the evil effects of electronic games. Henry Jenkins (2006) has pointed out however that much of the research refers to other media (like television), and that even the research specifically devoted to violence in video games is more equivocal:
To the extent that such studies have shown a correlation it has often been due to the fact that they have employed particular methodologies that are disposed to produce such correlations; Jenkins has discussed at length the influence of the media-effects school on the debate and John Sherry (2006) has analyzed the limitations of a reliance upon a dose-response research model. Indeed, the emphasis upon the violent effects of computer games proceeds from a long-lived attempt that couples moral policing of society with a fear of youth, and gives that a contemporary twist by attempting to greatly expand the states censorship capabilities [3, 4]. But there are two things that are interesting about this argument for the understanding of simulation specifically. First of all, electronic games are problematic for moral zealots precisely to the degree that they are understood as simulations. Lieutenant Colonel (Ret.) Dave Grossman (1999) for example, a fear merchant who briefly gained a degree of notoriety by feeding the moral panic that emerged in the wake of the Columbine murders, once (in)famously described first-person shooters such as Doom and Quake as murder simulators, a phrase that was at once picked up by a dutiful news media [5]. The second important point is evident from Grossmans choice of target games: games that are not conventionally classified as simulations by players, designers, industry analysts and scholars are seen unproblematically by the label em, ban em, burn em brigade as simulations. This was true in the wake of Columbine, when the target was FPS games, and it has been as true recently when the cross hairs have shifted first to Grand Theft Auto and then Manhunt 2. For these critics, it is decidedly not the representational content of the game nor its core gameplay that defines a game as a simulation. And it is most certainly not the realism of the representational content itself (a departure from the simplistic arguments deployed historically by such groups against books, theatre, film, comic books, etc.); indeed, many of the games targeted by these groups are patently fantastic in either setting or gameplay). Instead, the realism, and the simulational power of these games lies wholly in their ability to a) evoke and train realistic behavioral and emotional responses in a player, and b) encourage them to translate their game experience into real world behaviors. Simulation Fever A conflicted response to simulation is, however, as I have noted, built into the etymology of the word itself. Simulation is:
In other places and times (Pedagogia, Programma) I will argue (and may already have done so by the time you get there) that these troubling characteristics similarly define the application of simulation to the writing classroom. Simulation is the unnamed lurking presence that bedevils the teaching of writing. Some teachers do not want to admit that their classes are essentially simulations. The association of simulations with the counterfeit, with secondary activities such as copying and duplication, with behavioral training seem to render simulations the opposite of the first-year writing class. The operative paradigms for the writing class in fact appear to be very different: originality, authenticity, a concern with faithful represntation and the honing of the intellect. Other teachers, however, are all too aware that the problem with the traditional classroom is its simulative character. Thus, they seek to get beyond the idea of simulated writing instruction, away from the production of ersatz prose and toward writing that engages authentically with the real. In each case there is the fear of simulation as the force that destroys the distance between authenticity and the fake, that threatens to remove the distance between reality and its models, to assimilate students and teachers alike into a realm of false appearances. Yet there is one further characteristic of simulation that bears mention:
. . .what exactly? Are they harmonizing with the original referent of the simulation, or with the simulation itself? The confusion is troubling, no doubt, but it is this sense of simulation that is the basis of the effective learning techniques employed by MMORPGsand within which lurks the potential of the writing classroom if we embrace rather than run from its status as a simulative space. |
||
1. Frasca, G. (2003). Sim sin city: Some thoughts about Grand Theft Auto 3. Game Studies 3 (2). Retrieved March 25 2008. | ||
2. Jenkins, H. (2006) Coming up next! Ambushed on Donahue. Fans, bloggers, and gamers: Exploring participatory culture. New York: New York UP.
|
||
3. Sherry, J. (2006). Would the Great and Mighty Oz play Doom? : A look behind the curtain of violent video game research. In P. Messaris & L. Humphreys (Eds.), Digital media: Transformations in human communication (pp. 225-236). New York: Peter Lang. 4. Jenkins offers an additional framework with which to understand this debate: When culture warriors and media reformers cite examples of violent entertainment, they are almost always drawn to works that are explicitly struggling with the meaning of violence, works that have won critical acclaim or cult status in part because they break with the formulas through which our culture normally employs violence. They rarely cite the banal, formulaic, or aesthetically uninteresting works, though such works abound in the marketplace. It is as if the reformers are responding to the works own invitations to struggle with the costs and consequences of violence, yet their literal-minded critiques suggest an unwillingness to deal with those works with any degree of nuance. These works are condemned for what they depict, not examined for what they have to say (p. 216). Jenkins. H. The war between effects and meanings: rethinking the video game violence debate. In Fans, bloggers, and gamers. 209-217. 5. Grossman, Lt. Col. D. and Degaetano, G. (1999) Stop teaching our kids to kill: A call to action against TV, movie, and vide0 game violence. New York: Crown Publishers. |
||
Pack Up and Move to a New City |